Gendlin’s “reversal” and the history of metaphor theories—Richards, Black, and Merleau-Ponty
In his paper on the theory and practice of Focusing, Akira Ikemi discussed the order in which a metaphorical expression and the similarities, likenesses, or commonalities between the things being compared within the expression are presented as follows:
Why did Gendlin insist on this order? I will begin my discussion by examining its historical background.
Reversal of the order: metaphor and similarity
In “A Process Model (APM)” (Gendlin, 1997/2018), the ideas formulated in “Experiencing and the Creation of Meaning (ECM)” (Gendlin, 1962/1997) were applied and expanded in various ways. A typical example is his metaphor theory. Let us quote from APM:
After discussing the above, he stated that “we reversed the order” (Gendlin, 1997/2018, p. 51) by his earlier work, ECM. In Chapter IV of ECM, he presented “Reversal of the usual philosophic procedure” (Gendlin, 1962/1997, pp. 140–4) and already stated as follows:
However, assuming that Gendlin alone conceived of the reversal would be dangerous and erroneous. Therefore, let us trace how earlier thinkers or philosophers prepared the “reversal” and how he developed the argument.
Prehistory of the reversal: Richards and Black
The English literary critic and thinker Ivor A. Richards (1893–1979), in his classic masterpiece “The Philosophy of Rhetoric,” specifically discussed metaphor as follows:
The “common characteristics” referred to here as the “ground” is what has long been called in Latin “tertium comparationis” (the third [part] of the comparison). In insisting that metaphors can work without being able to say what the common characteristics are, Richards can be said to be one who prepared Gendlin’s “reversal.” What is unfortunate, however, is that Richards called the characteristics the “ground.” Contrary to the discussion above, this naming gave the impression that the common characteristics had been explicitly stated beforehand and that the metaphor could only work based on the explicit characteristics. Such an impression is at odds with the “reversal.”
Richards’ discussion was called “an interaction view of metaphor” (Black, 1955, p. 285; 1981, p. 72) by an analytic philosopher in the English-speaking world, Max Black (1909–1988). Black saw himself as belonging to this lineage and took over and developed the view. Three years before Gendlin wrote his doctoral dissertation (Gendlin, 1958) as the original ECM, Black had already argued as follows:
In this way, Black further prepared Gendlin’s “reversal” by making Richards’ argument thorough.
Prehistory of the reversal: Merleau-Ponty
I would also like to mention Maurice Merleau-Ponty (1908-1961) as a French philosopher who prepared Gendlin’s “reversal” without the influence of Richards or Black.
Merleau-Ponty often discussed reports of a patient who suffered brain damage during World War I, known as Schneider. In his seminal work, “Phenomenology of Perception,” he discussed a case in which Schneider could not understand metaphors and analogies. In my view, this discussion is very helpful in understanding the contrast between “the usual philosophic procedure” and “the reversal of the procedure” through concrete examples.
Merleau-Ponty summarized Schneider’s case based on the report in Benary (1922):
This means that contrary to Richards’ assumption, such metaphors do not work in this patient’s case.
In other words, metaphors and analogies do not work at all for the patient until he makes explicit the common characteristics, such as “… both sense organs.”
On the other hand, regarding the normal subjects, he discussed as follows:
This means that the analogy can work without going through the “roundabout way” (Merleau-Ponty, 1962, p. 128; cf. 1945, p. 149) of the explicit characteristics— “tertium comparationis” (Benary, 1922, p. 263; Merleau-Ponty, 1962, p. 128; cf. 1945, p. 148).
According to Gendlin’s metaphor theory, the patient’s thinking process follows “the usual philosophic procedure,” whereas the normal subject’s thinking process follows “the reversal of the procedure.” Thus, I consider Merleau-Ponty to be one of those who prepared Gendlin’s “reversal.”
Succession and development by Gendlin
Following his predecessors, Gendlin discussed the writing process of the poet (possibly Scottish poet Robert Burns) who created the metaphoric line “My love is like a red, red rose” in ECM. Usually, when examining such creative processes, “The old philosophic procedure tempts us” that “The likeness to ‘red, red rose’ appears to determine just what aspect of ‘my love’ will be newly created by the metaphor” (Gendlin, 1962/1997, p. 142). But we should reverse the procedure, he argued:
The order is that the rose is first found as something implicitly similar to the lover before the characteristics are explicitly present as likenesses — “fresh, blooming, eventually passing, beautiful, living, tender, attractive, soft, quietly waiting to be picked, part of greater nature” (Gendlin, 1962/1997, p. 142).
Gendlin later summarized his theory of metaphor in his paper “Crossing and Dipping,” which offers a specific consideration as follows:
If the characteristics had been explicitly stated beforehand, we would have been able to mention them before hearing the metaphor. However, that was not the case, and the characteristics were only derived as common features after it was implicitly felt that a cigarette was somewhat similar to a time bomb.
The idea that features or traits were not explicitly present beforehand continued to be considered in APM:
Applying the earlier cigarette example to the argument above, by speaking of a cigarette as if it were a time bomb, certain aspects of a cigarette are made which were not there before as such. The metaphor does not “select” this trait from a list of existing traits of a cigarette; there is no such fixed set.
Next, let us go back in time and consider the argument in ECM:
In other words, we can ask: What is the new sort of “symbolization” between the symbols of B and the new aspect of the old experience of A? To put it further, we can also say that by speaking of “my love” as if it were “a red, red rose", certain aspects of “my love” are made which were not there before as such.
Let’s see how he discussed, with other examples, the characteristics or traits that emerge beyond any prior expectations when two things are crossed.
The example above was discussed by Shimpei Okamura, who wrote his doctoral dissertation on Gendlin’s theory of metaphor as follows:
A similar example is given in APM:
Again, you can see that the features only became explicit after the toothbrushes were crossed with the trains.
Conclusion
Gendlin reiterated his metaphor theory even after ECM as follows:
Black explored the “reversal” of the order, but his discussion was limited to linguistic analysis in the tradition of analytic philosophy. Merleau-Ponty, on the other hand, extended the reversal to the preconceptual experience. Whereas Merleau-Ponty discussed only the hearer or reader’s processes of the metaphor, Gendlin extended his discussion to the speaker or writer’s processes of the metaphor (cf. Tanaka, 2023, August). Moreover, in APM, he applied this idea of the reversal to his discussion of the various stages of living processes, such as plants and animals.
Note
*1) If the metaphor “My love is like a red, red rose” creates likenesses such as “fresh, blooming, eventually passing, beautiful, living, tender, attractive, soft, quietly waiting to be picked, part of greater nature,” then such explicit likenesses can be called “new thirds” or “new third universals,” according to APM terminology.
References
Benary, W. (1922). Studien zur Untersuchung der Intelligenz bei einem Fall von Seelenblindheit. Psychologische Forschung, 2, 208-97.
Black, M. (1955). Metaphor. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 55(1), 273–94. Reprinted as Black, M. (1981). Metaphor. M. Johnson (ed.) Philosophical perspectives on metaphor (pp. 63–82). University of Minnesota Press.
Gendlin, E.T. (1958). The function of experiencing in symbolization. Doctoral dissertation. University of Chicago.
Gendlin, E.T. (1962/1997). Experiencing and the creation of meaning: a philosophical and psychological approach to the subjective (Paper ed.). Northwestern University Press.
Gendlin, E.T. (1986). Let your body interpret your dreams. Chiron.
Gendlin, E.T. (1988). Dwelling. In H.J. Silverman, A. Mickunas, T. Kisiel, & A. Lingis (Eds.), The Horizons of continental philosophy: essays on Husserl, Heidegger, and Merleau-Ponty (pp. 133-52). Kluwer Academic.
Gendlin, E.T. (1995). Crossing and dipping: some terms for approaching the interface between natural understanding and logical formulation. Minds and Machines, 5(4), 547-60.
Gendlin, E.T. (1997). Reply to Johnson. In D.M. Levin (Ed.), Language beyond postmodernism: saying and thinking in Gendlin’s philosophy (pp. 168–75 & 357–58). Northwestern University Press.
Gendlin, E.T. (1997/2018). A process model. Northwestern University Press.
Ikemi, A. (2017). The radical impact of experiencing on psychotherapy theory: an examination of two kinds of crossings. Person-Centered and Experiential Psychotherapies, 16(2), 159–72.
Johnson, M. (1987). The body in the mind: the bodily basis of meaning, imagination, and reason. University of Chicago Press.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception (C. Smith, trans.). Humanities Press. Originally published as Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945). Phénoménologie de la perception. Gallimard.
Okamura, S. (2016). The creativity of wordplay: a consideration from Gendlin’s conception of ‘crossing’ [in Japanese]. Studies in Integral Humanities, 1, 55–63.
Richards, I.A. (1936). The philosophy of rhetoric. Oxford University Press.
Tanaka, H. (2023, August). Comprehension and Metaphor in “Experiencing and the Creation of Meaning” (Gendlin, 1962/1997).
Thorgeirsdottir, S. (2023). Liberating language: Gendlin and Nietzsche on the refreshing power of metaphors. In E. Severson & K. Krycka (eds.), The psychology and philosophy of Eugene Gendlin: making sense of contemporary experience (pp. 85–101). Routledge.